Proseminar SoSe 2001: Ethischer Relativismus
Handout 2: Ethical relativism
is the doctrine that the moral rightness and wrongness of actions varies from
society to society and that there are no absolute universal moral standards
binding on all men at all times. Accordingly, it holds that whether or not it
is right for an individual to act in a certain way depends on or is relative to
the society to which he belongs. (John Ladd (Hrsg.), Ethical Relativism,
Belmont 1973, S. 1, zitiert aus Louis P. Pojman, Ethics. Discovering Right
and Wrong, Belmont 1990, S. 20) Deskriptiver
Relativismus: Es gibt eine
große Diversität der Werte und moralischen Überzeugungen, die von Menschen (in
verschiedenen Kulturen und in verschiedenen Zeitaltern) vertreten werden, wobei
diese unterschiedlichen Werte und moralischen Überzeugungen auf fundamentale
Weise konfligieren. Fundamentale
Meinungsunterschiede bezüglich Werten und moralischen Überzeugungen bestehen,
wenn (a) die unterschiedlichen Werte und moralischen
Überzeugungen nicht durch unterschiedliche Meinungen über die Natur, das
Verhältnis der Menschen zur Natur, die menschliche Natur, die beiden
Geschlechter, die Religion usw. erklärt werden können, (b) die Meinungsunterschiede nicht durch
unterschiedliche äußere Bedingungen erklärt werden können, so daß die gleichen
Werte und Moralprinzipien nur unter unterschiedlichen Bedingungen angewandt
werden. Metaethischer
Relativismus: Es gibt nicht
eine einzige wahre bzw. am besten begründete Moral, deren Prinzipien für alle
Menschen gelten (unabhängig davon, ob sie tatsächlich von allen Menschen
anerkannt werden). Moralurteile
sind wahr oder falsch relativ zu bestimmten Kulturen. Normativer
Relativismus: Es ist moralisch
falsch, (a) das Verhalten und die Praktiken von Menschen
und Kulturen mit anderen Moralvorstellungen moralisch zu beurteilen und (b) sich in deren Angelegenheiten einzumischen. Kulturrelativismus: 1. Variante des deskriptiven Relativismus: Die fundamentalen Meinungsunterschiede hinsichtlich Werten
und moralischen Überzeugungen sind kulturabhängig. 2. Variante des metaethischen Relativismus: The moral
theory of cultural relativism, roughly put, is this: Although for every culture some moral
judgements are valid, no moral judgement is universally valid, meaning
valid for all cultures. Instead, every moral judgement is culturally relative.
(John J. Tilley (1998): Culturalism Relativism, Universalism, and the Burden of
Proof, Millennium 27, S. 275-97: S. 275) Absolutismus: 1. Es gibt eine einzige wahre bzw. am besten
begründete Moral, deren Prinzipien für alle Menschen gelten (unabhängig davon,
ob sie tatsächlich von allen Menschen anerkannt werden). 2. Es gibt bestimmte Handlungsweisen, die unter
allen Umständen, d. h. unabhängig von allen Konsequenzen verboten oder
geboten sind. Anders formuliert: Es gibt bestimmte moralische Regeln, die ausnahmslos
gelten, d. h. die unter keinen Umständen verletzt werden dürfen. Universalismus: 1. Einige Moralurteile sind universell gültig
(d. h. sie gelten für alle Menschen). 2. Alle Menschen sind in moralischer Hinsicht
gleich. Die Zugehörigkeit zu bestimmten Gruppen wie Nation, Rasse, Klasse,
Geschlecht usw. rechtfertigt keine unterschiedliche Behandlung der Menschen: As
a first approximation, ethical universalism may be defined as the doctrine that
all persons ought to be treated with equal and impartial positive consideration
for their respective goods or interests. [...] according to ethical
particularism, one ought to give preferential consideration to the interests of
some persons as against others, including not only oneself but also other
persons with whom one has special relationships, such as for example, the
members of one's own family or friendship circle or local community or nation
or various other restricted social groups. (Alan Gewirth, Ethical Universalism
and Particularism, Journal of Philosophy 85 (1988), S. 283-302: S. 283) Objektivismus: objectivism The general idea that what binds people in
morality binds them independently of any particular person's or group of
persons' belief or opinion. (J. Carl Ficarrotta (1998): Moral Relativism, in Encyclopedia
of Applied Ethics, hrsg. von Ruth Chadwick, San Diego, Vol. 3, S. 275-88: S.
275) Ethical
objectivists [...] hold that the validity of moral judgments depends on factors
independent of human beings and that moral judgments are true or false
regardless of what human beings think about them. (C. E. Harris, Jr. (1992): Applying Moral Theories, 2.
Aufl., Belmont, Cal., S. 35f.) When applied to morality, the terms
'objective' and 'subjective' each connote a family of characteristics. That
is, the characteristics are not necessarily related but are frequently found
together in descriptions of the nature of morality. When a philosopher calls
morality objective, for instance, he or she is making several and perhaps all
of the following claims: 1. Moral
statements have truth values; 2. There are
good and bad arguments for the moral positions people take; 3. Nonmoral facts (states of affairs that obtain
in the world and that can be described without use of moral terms such as
'ought,' 'good,' and 'right') are relevant to the assessment of the truth value
of moral statements; 4. There are moral facts (that may or may not be
claimed to be reducible in some way to nonmoral facts); 5. When two
moral statements conflict as recommendations to action, only one statement can
be true; 6. There is a
single true morality. When
morality is called subjective, several and perhaps all of the above claims are
denied. (David B. Wong (1984): Moral Relativity, Berkeley, S. 1f.) It is commonly assumed that any plausible conception
of objectivity must establish that there is a reliable connection between any
inquiry described as objective and some realm that exists independent of that
inquiry. Yet this assumption unwisely ignores the grammar, in the
Wittgensteinian sense, of the concept of objectivity. For to assert the
objectivity of any human inquiry is, first of all, to affirm the possibility
that the results of that inquiry might transcend the "intensely human" limitations
of its methods. Any claim that some inquiry is objective thus embodies an aspiration to the transcendent validity
of the outcome of inquiry. Acknowledging this link between objectivity and
human aspirations, moreover, helps illuminate familiar concerns about
objectivity in everyday life. An interviewer who seeks objective assessments of
applicants for a job, like judges in a piano competition who seek objective
grounds for choosing a winner or a professor who seeks to assess student essays
objectively, aspires to results which transcend the limitations of her
preconceptions and unreflective preferences. In each case objectivity demands
reliance on grounds of assessment that can be justified to any reasonable and
qualified judge. Ideally, objectivity demands that methods of inquiry entirely
eliminate the influence of the narrowly personal perspective of the inquiring
subject - even though in most everyday inquiries objectivity is always a
matter of degree, a function of the extent to which the methods of
inquiry effectively minimize the
perspective of the inquiring subject. [...] [...] it is important to
note a second crucial feature of the grammar of the concept of objectivity. For
any claim that some inquiry is objective also implicitly asserts that it is
possible to secure uncoerced agreement on at least some results of that
inquiry. In fact, the occurrence of uncoerced agreement on some conclusion
often serves - and I think reasonably - to bolster confidence in aspirations to
transcendent validity, and hence in the objectivity of the inquiry in
question. This is most obvious, perhaps, in the informal inquiries of everyday
life. Thus, the professor whose colleagues without prompting second her
assessment of an essay reasonably concludes that her assessment meets the demands
of objectivity appropriate to the inquiry. But important defenses of the
objectivity of science cite the regularity of uncoerced agreement in science as
compelling evidence that science's aspirations to transcendent validity are
rational. (Michele M.
Moody-Adams (1997): Fieldwork in
Familiar Places. Morality, Culture, and Philosophy, Cambridge, Mass., S.
178f.) Objective knowledge is commonly thought to require
belief, truth, and justification. Following this understanding, let us say that
a person knows a moral proposition (for example, that we ought to change
an unfair policy) only if the person believes it, it is true, and the person
is justified in believing it. On this account, asserting that the proposition
is true should be understood in a straightforward sense at least in many
respects similar to the sense of "true" in statements such as "It is true that
the wolves have returned." Thus, the truth of a proposition is usually independent
of the attitudes people happen to have towards it. Saying that a person is
justified in believing a proposition means that the person has sufficient
evidence, reasons, grounds, etc. for believing it is true in this sense. Now,
let us say that morality is objective only if the following three
conditions obtain: (a) moral propositions are ordinarily true or false (they
have "truth-value"); (b) many moral propositions are true; and (c) persons have
the capacity to be, and in fact often are, justified in believing moral
propositions (specifically, believing true ones and disbelieving false ones).
On this conception, moral objectivists believe that morality is objective,
while moral nonobjectivists deny this because they think either that moral
propositions are never true or that no one is ever justified in believing moral
propositions (or both). (Christopher
W. Gowans (2000): Introduction: Debates about Moral Disagreements, in Moral
Disagreements. Classic and Contemporary Readings, hrsg. von Christopher W.
Gowans, London, S. 1-43: S. 3) |